Theory Probability_Logic
chapter ‹ Probability Logic \label{chapter:probability} ›
theory Probability_Logic
imports
"Propositional_Logic_Class.Classical_Connectives"
HOL.Real
"HOL-Library.Countable"
begin
unbundle no funcset_syntax
section ‹ Definition of Probability Logic \label{sec:definition-of-probability-logic} ›
text ‹ Probability logic is defined in terms of an operator over
classical logic obeying certain postulates. Scholars often credit
George Boole for first conceiving this kind of formulation @{cite booleChapterXVITheory1853}.
Theodore Hailperin in particular has written extensively on this subject
@{cite hailperinProbabilityLogic1984
and hailperinBooleLogicProbability1986
and hailperinSententialProbabilityLogic1996}. ›
text ‹ The presentation below roughly follows Kolmogorov's axiomatization
@{cite kolmogoroffChapterElementareWahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung1933}.
A key difference is that we only require ∗‹finite additivity›, rather
than ∗‹countable additivity›. Finite additivity is also defined in
terms of implication \<^term>‹(→)›. ›
class probability_logic = classical_logic +
fixes 𝒫 :: "'a ⇒ real"
assumes probability_non_negative: "𝒫 φ ≥ 0"
assumes probability_unity: "⊢ φ ⟹ 𝒫 φ = 1"
assumes probability_implicational_additivity:
"⊢ φ → ψ → ⊥ ⟹ 𝒫 ((φ → ⊥) → ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ"
text ‹ A similar axiomatization may be credited to
Rescher @{cite ‹pg. 185› rescherManyvaluedLogic1969}.
However, our formulation has fewer axioms.
While Rescher assumes \<^term>‹⊢ φ ↔ ψ ⟹ 𝒫 φ = 𝒫 ψ›, we
show this is a lemma in \S\ref{sec:prob-logic-alt-def}. ›
section ‹ Why Finite Additivity? \label{section:why-finite-additivity} ›
text ‹ In this section we touch on why we have chosen to
employ finite additivity in our axiomatization of
@{class probability_logic} and deviate from conventional
probability theory. ›
text ‹ Conventional probability obeys an axiom known as ∗‹countable additivity›.
Traditionally it states if ‹S› is a countable set of sets which are
pairwise disjoint, then the limit ‹∑ s ∈ S. 𝒫 s› exists and
‹𝒫 (⋃ S) = (∑ s ∈ S. 𝒫 s)›. This is more powerful than our
finite additivity axiom
@{lemma ‹⊢ φ → ψ → ⊥ ⟹ 𝒫 ((φ → ⊥) → ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ›
by (metis probability_implicational_additivity) }. ›
text ‹ However, we argue that demanding countable additivity is not practical. ›
text ‹ Historically, the statisticians Bruno de Finetti and Leonard Savage
gave the most well known critiques. In @{cite definettiSuiPassaggiLimite1930}
de Finetti shows various properties which are true for countably additive
probability measures may not hold for finitely additive measures.
Savage @{cite savageDifficultiesTheoryPersonal1967}, on the other hand,
develops probability based on choices prizes in lotteries. ›
text ‹ We instead argue that if we demand countable additivity, then certain
properties of real world software would no longer be formally verifiable
as we demonstrate here. In particular, it prohibits conventional recursive
data structures for defining propositions. Our argument is derivative of
one given by Giangiacomo Gerla @{cite ‹Section 3› gerlaInferencesProbabilityLogic1994}. ›
text ‹ By taking equivalence classes modulo \<^term>‹λ φ ψ . ⊢ φ ↔ ψ›,
any classical logic instance gives rise to a Boolean algebra known as
a ∗‹Lindenbaum Algebra›. In the case of @{typ "'a classical_propositional_formula"}
this Boolean algebra algebra is both countable and ∗‹atomless›.
A theorem of Horn and Tarski @{cite ‹Theorem 3.2› hornMeasuresBooleanAlgebras1948}
asserts there can be no countably additive \<^term>‹Pr› for a countable
atomless Boolean algebra. ›
text ‹ The above argument is not intended as a blanket refutation of conventional
probability theory. It is simply an impossibility result with respect
to software implementations of probability logic. Plenty of classic results
in probability rely on countable additivity. A nice example, formalized in
Isabelle/HOL, is Bouffon's needle @{cite eberlBuffonNeedleProblem2017}. ›
section ‹ Basic Properties of Probability Logic ›
lemma (in probability_logic) probability_additivity:
assumes "⊢ ∼ (φ ⊓ ψ)"
shows "𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ"
using
assms
unfolding
conjunction_def
disjunction_def
negation_def
by (simp add: probability_implicational_additivity)
lemma (in probability_logic) probability_alternate_additivity:
assumes "⊢ φ → ψ → ⊥"
shows "𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ"
using assms
by (metis
probability_additivity
double_negation_converse
modus_ponens
conjunction_def
negation_def)
lemma (in probability_logic) complementation:
"𝒫 (∼ φ) = 1 - 𝒫 φ"
by (metis
probability_alternate_additivity
probability_unity
bivalence
negation_elimination
add.commute
add_diff_cancel_left')
lemma (in probability_logic) unity_upper_bound:
"𝒫 φ ≤ 1"
by (metis
(no_types)
diff_ge_0_iff_ge
probability_non_negative
complementation)
section ‹ Alternate Definition of Probability Logic \label{sec:prob-logic-alt-def} ›
text ‹ There is an alternate axiomatization of probability logic,
due to Brian Gaines @{cite ‹pg. 159, postulates P7, P8, and P8› gainesFuzzyProbabilityUncertainty1978}
and independently formulated by Brian Weatherson @{cite weathersonClassicalIntuitionisticProbability2003}.
As Weatherson notes, this axiomatization is suited to formulating
∗‹intuitionistic› probability logic. In the case where the underlying
logic is classical the Gaines/Weatherson axiomatization is equivalent
to the traditional Kolmogorov axiomatization from
\S\ref{sec:definition-of-probability-logic}. ›
class gaines_weatherson_probability = classical_logic +
fixes 𝒫 :: "'a ⇒ real"
assumes gaines_weatherson_thesis:
"𝒫 ⊤ = 1"
assumes gaines_weatherson_antithesis:
"𝒫 ⊥ = 0"
assumes gaines_weatherson_monotonicity:
"⊢ φ → ψ ⟹ 𝒫 φ ≤ 𝒫 ψ"
assumes gaines_weatherson_sum_rule:
"𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ = 𝒫 (φ ⊓ ψ) + 𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ)"
sublocale gaines_weatherson_probability ⊆ probability_logic
proof
fix φ
have "⊢ ⊥ → φ"
by (simp add: ex_falso_quodlibet)
thus "0 ≤ 𝒫 φ"
using
gaines_weatherson_antithesis
gaines_weatherson_monotonicity
by fastforce
next
fix φ
assume "⊢ φ"
thus "𝒫 φ = 1"
by (metis
gaines_weatherson_thesis
gaines_weatherson_monotonicity
eq_iff
axiom_k
ex_falso_quodlibet
modus_ponens
verum_def)
next
fix φ ψ
assume "⊢ φ → ψ → ⊥"
hence "⊢ ∼ (φ ⊓ ψ)"
by (simp add: conjunction_def negation_def)
thus "𝒫 ((φ → ⊥) → ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ"
by (metis
add.commute
add.right_neutral
eq_iff
disjunction_def
ex_falso_quodlibet
negation_def
gaines_weatherson_antithesis
gaines_weatherson_monotonicity
gaines_weatherson_sum_rule)
qed
lemma (in probability_logic) monotonicity:
"⊢ φ → ψ ⟹ 𝒫 φ ≤ 𝒫 ψ"
proof -
assume "⊢ φ → ψ"
hence "⊢ ∼ (φ ⊓ ∼ ψ)"
unfolding negation_def conjunction_def
by (metis
conjunction_def
exclusion_contrapositive_equivalence
negation_def
weak_biconditional_weaken)
hence "𝒫 (φ ⊔ ∼ ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 (∼ ψ)"
by (simp add: probability_additivity)
hence "𝒫 φ + 𝒫 (∼ ψ) ≤ 1"
by (metis unity_upper_bound)
hence "𝒫 φ + 1 - 𝒫 ψ ≤ 1"
by (simp add: complementation)
thus ?thesis by linarith
qed
lemma (in probability_logic) biconditional_equivalence:
"⊢ φ ↔ ψ ⟹ 𝒫 φ = 𝒫 ψ"
by (meson
eq_iff
modus_ponens
biconditional_left_elimination
biconditional_right_elimination
monotonicity)
lemma (in probability_logic) sum_rule:
"𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) + 𝒫 (φ ⊓ ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ"
proof -
have "⊢ (φ ⊔ ψ) ↔ (φ ⊔ ψ ∖ (φ ⊓ ψ))"
proof -
have "∀ 𝔐. 𝔐 ⊨⇩p⇩r⇩o⇩p (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊔ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ↔ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊔ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ∖ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩))"
unfolding
classical_logic_class.subtraction_def
classical_logic_class.negation_def
classical_logic_class.biconditional_def
classical_logic_class.conjunction_def
classical_logic_class.disjunction_def
by simp
hence "⊢ ❙⦇ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊔ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ↔ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊔ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ∖ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩)) ❙⦈"
using propositional_semantics by blast
thus ?thesis by simp
qed
moreover have "⊢ φ → (ψ ∖ (φ ⊓ ψ)) → ⊥"
proof -
have "∀ 𝔐. 𝔐 ⊨⇩p⇩r⇩o⇩p ❙⟨φ❙⟩ → (❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ∖ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩)) → ⊥"
unfolding
classical_logic_class.subtraction_def
classical_logic_class.negation_def
classical_logic_class.biconditional_def
classical_logic_class.conjunction_def
classical_logic_class.disjunction_def
by simp
hence "⊢ ❙⦇ ❙⟨φ❙⟩ → (❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ∖ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩)) → ⊥ ❙⦈"
using propositional_semantics by blast
thus ?thesis by simp
qed
hence "𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 (ψ ∖ (φ ⊓ ψ))"
using
probability_alternate_additivity
biconditional_equivalence
calculation
by auto
moreover have "⊢ ψ ↔ (ψ ∖ (φ ⊓ ψ) ⊔ (φ ⊓ ψ))"
proof -
have "∀ 𝔐. 𝔐 ⊨⇩p⇩r⇩o⇩p ❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ↔ (❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ∖ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ⊔ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩))"
unfolding
classical_logic_class.subtraction_def
classical_logic_class.negation_def
classical_logic_class.biconditional_def
classical_logic_class.conjunction_def
classical_logic_class.disjunction_def
by auto
hence "⊢ ❙⦇ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ↔ (❙⟨ψ❙⟩ ∖ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ⊔ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩)) ❙⦈"
using propositional_semantics by
blast
thus ?thesis by simp
qed
moreover have "⊢ (ψ ∖ (φ ⊓ ψ)) → (φ ⊓ ψ) → ⊥"
unfolding
subtraction_def
negation_def
conjunction_def
using
conjunction_def
conjunction_right_elimination
by auto
hence "𝒫 ψ = 𝒫 (ψ ∖ (φ ⊓ ψ)) + 𝒫 (φ ⊓ ψ)"
using
probability_alternate_additivity
biconditional_equivalence
calculation
by auto
ultimately show ?thesis
by simp
qed
sublocale probability_logic ⊆ gaines_weatherson_probability
proof
show "𝒫 ⊤ = 1"
by (simp add: probability_unity)
next
show "𝒫 ⊥ = 0"
by (metis
add_cancel_left_right
probability_additivity
ex_falso_quodlibet
probability_unity
bivalence
conjunction_right_elimination
negation_def)
next
fix φ ψ
assume "⊢ φ → ψ"
thus "𝒫 φ ≤ 𝒫 ψ"
using monotonicity
by auto
next
fix φ ψ
show "𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ = 𝒫 (φ ⊓ ψ) + 𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ)"
by (metis sum_rule add.commute)
qed
sublocale probability_logic ⊆ consistent_classical_logic
proof
show "¬ ⊢ ⊥" using probability_unity gaines_weatherson_antithesis by auto
qed
lemma (in probability_logic) subtraction_identity:
"𝒫 (φ ∖ ψ) = 𝒫 φ - 𝒫 (φ ⊓ ψ)"
proof -
have "⊢ φ ↔ ((φ ∖ ψ) ⊔ (φ ⊓ ψ))"
proof -
have "∀ 𝔐. 𝔐 ⊨⇩p⇩r⇩o⇩p ❙⟨φ❙⟩ ↔ ((❙⟨φ❙⟩ ∖ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ⊔ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩))"
unfolding
classical_logic_class.subtraction_def
classical_logic_class.negation_def
classical_logic_class.biconditional_def
classical_logic_class.conjunction_def
classical_logic_class.disjunction_def
by (simp, blast)
hence "⊢ ❙⦇ ❙⟨φ❙⟩ ↔ ((❙⟨φ❙⟩ ∖ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ⊔ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩)) ❙⦈"
using propositional_semantics by blast
thus ?thesis by simp
qed
hence "𝒫 φ = 𝒫 ((φ ∖ ψ) ⊔ (φ ⊓ ψ))"
using biconditional_equivalence
by simp
moreover have "⊢ ∼((φ ∖ ψ) ⊓ (φ ⊓ ψ))"
proof -
have "∀ 𝔐. 𝔐 ⊨⇩p⇩r⇩o⇩p ∼((❙⟨φ❙⟩ ∖ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ⊓ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩))"
unfolding
classical_logic_class.subtraction_def
classical_logic_class.negation_def
classical_logic_class.conjunction_def
classical_logic_class.disjunction_def
by simp
hence "⊢ ❙⦇ ∼((❙⟨φ❙⟩ ∖ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩) ⊓ (❙⟨φ❙⟩ ⊓ ❙⟨ψ❙⟩)) ❙⦈"
using propositional_semantics by blast
thus ?thesis by simp
qed
ultimately show ?thesis
using probability_additivity
by auto
qed
section ‹ Basic Probability Logic Inequality Results \label{sec:basic-probability-inequality-results}›
lemma (in probability_logic) disjunction_sum_inequality:
"𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) ≤ 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ"
proof -
have "𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) + 𝒫 (φ ⊓ ψ) = 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 ψ"
"0 ≤ 𝒫 (φ ⊓ ψ)"
by (simp add: sum_rule, simp add: probability_non_negative)
thus ?thesis by linarith
qed
lemma (in probability_logic)
arbitrary_disjunction_list_summation_inequality:
"𝒫 (⨆ Φ) ≤ (∑φ←Φ. 𝒫 φ)"
proof (induct Φ)
case Nil
then show ?case by (simp add: gaines_weatherson_antithesis)
next
case (Cons φ Φ)
have "𝒫 (⨆ (φ # Φ)) ≤ 𝒫 φ + 𝒫 (⨆ Φ)"
using disjunction_sum_inequality
by simp
with Cons have "𝒫 (⨆ (φ # Φ)) ≤ 𝒫 φ + (∑φ←Φ. 𝒫 φ)" by linarith
then show ?case by simp
qed
lemma (in probability_logic) implication_list_summation_inequality:
assumes "⊢ φ → ⨆ Ψ"
shows "𝒫 φ ≤ (∑ψ←Ψ. 𝒫 ψ)"
using
assms
arbitrary_disjunction_list_summation_inequality
monotonicity
order_trans
by blast
lemma (in probability_logic) arbitrary_disjunction_set_summation_inequality:
"𝒫 (⨆ Φ) ≤ (∑φ ∈ set Φ. 𝒫 φ)"
by (metis
arbitrary_disjunction_list_summation_inequality
arbitrary_disjunction_remdups
biconditional_equivalence
sum.set_conv_list)
lemma (in probability_logic) implication_set_summation_inequality:
assumes "⊢ φ → ⨆ Ψ"
shows "𝒫 φ ≤ (∑ψ ∈ set Ψ. 𝒫 ψ)"
using
assms
arbitrary_disjunction_set_summation_inequality
monotonicity
order_trans
by blast
section ‹ Dirac Measures \label{sec:dirac-measures}›
text ‹ Before presenting ∗‹Dirac measures› in probability logic, we first
give the set of all functions satisfying probability logic.›
definition (in classical_logic) probabilities :: "('a ⇒ real) set"
where "probabilities =
{𝒫. class.probability_logic (λ φ. ⊢ φ) (→) ⊥ 𝒫 }"
text ‹ Traditionally, a Dirac measure is a function \<^term>‹δ⇩x› where
\<^term>‹δ⇩x(S) = (1::real)› if \<^term>‹x ∈ S› and \<^term>‹δ⇩x(S) = (0::real)›
otherwise. This means that Dirac measures correspond to special
ultrafilters on their underlying \<^term>‹σ›-algebra which are
closed under countable unions. ›
text ‹ Probability logic, as discussed in \S\ref{section:why-finite-additivity},
may not have countable joins in its underlying logic. In the setting
of probability logic, Dirac measures are simple probability functions
that are either 0 or 1. ›
definition (in classical_logic) dirac_measures :: "('a ⇒ real) set"
where "dirac_measures =
{ 𝒫. class.probability_logic (λ φ. ⊢ φ) (→) ⊥ 𝒫
∧ (∀x. 𝒫 x = 0 ∨ 𝒫 x = 1) }"
lemma (in classical_logic) dirac_measures_subset:
"dirac_measures ⊆ probabilities"
unfolding
probabilities_def
dirac_measures_def
by fastforce
text ‹ Maximally consistent sets correspond to Dirac measures. One direction
of this correspondence is established below. ›
lemma (in classical_logic) MCS_dirac_measure:
assumes "MCS Ω"
shows "(λ χ. if χ∈Ω then (1 :: real) else 0) ∈ dirac_measures"
(is "?𝒫 ∈ dirac_measures")
proof -
have "class.probability_logic (λ φ. ⊢ φ) (→) ⊥ ?𝒫"
proof (standard, simp,
meson
assms
formula_maximally_consistent_set_def_reflection
maximally_consistent_set_def
set_deduction_weaken)
fix φ ψ
assume "⊢ φ → ψ → ⊥"
hence "φ ⊓ ψ ∉ Ω"
by (metis
assms
formula_consistent_def
formula_maximally_consistent_set_def_def
maximally_consistent_set_def
conjunction_def
set_deduction_modus_ponens
set_deduction_reflection
set_deduction_weaken)
hence "φ ∉ Ω ∨ ψ ∉ Ω"
using
assms
formula_maximally_consistent_set_def_reflection
maximally_consistent_set_def
conjunction_set_deduction_equivalence
by meson
have "φ ⊔ ψ ∈ Ω = (φ ∈ Ω ∨ ψ ∈ Ω)"
by (metis
‹φ ⊓ ψ ∉ Ω›
assms
formula_maximally_consistent_set_def_implication
maximally_consistent_set_def
conjunction_def
disjunction_def)
have "?𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) = ?𝒫 φ + ?𝒫 ψ"
proof (cases "φ ⊔ ψ ∈ Ω")
case True
hence ♢: "1 = ?𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ)" by simp
show ?thesis
proof (cases "φ ∈ Ω")
case True
hence "ψ ∉ Ω"
using ‹φ ∉ Ω ∨ ψ ∉ Ω›
by blast
have "?𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) = (1::real)" using ♢ by simp
also have "... = 1 + (0::real)" by linarith
also have "... = ?𝒫 φ + ?𝒫 ψ"
using ‹ψ ∉ Ω› ‹φ ∈ Ω› by simp
finally show ?thesis .
next
case False
hence "ψ ∈ Ω"
using ‹φ ⊔ ψ ∈ Ω› ‹(φ ⊔ ψ ∈ Ω) = (φ ∈ Ω ∨ ψ ∈ Ω)›
by blast
have "?𝒫 (φ ⊔ ψ) = (1::real)" using ♢ by simp
also have "... = (0::real) + 1" by linarith
also have "... = ?𝒫 φ + ?𝒫 ψ"
using ‹ψ ∈ Ω› ‹φ ∉ Ω› by simp
finally show ?thesis .
qed
next
case False
moreover from this have "φ ∉ Ω" "ψ ∉ Ω"
using ‹(φ ⊔ ψ ∈ Ω) = (φ ∈ Ω ∨ ψ ∈ Ω)› by blast+
ultimately show ?thesis by simp
qed
thus "?𝒫 ((φ → ⊥) → ψ) = ?𝒫 φ + ?𝒫 ψ"
unfolding disjunction_def .
qed
thus ?thesis
unfolding dirac_measures_def
by simp
qed
unbundle funcset_syntax
end